Montesquieu
The
Godfather of the American Constitution
First novels are often erotic and almost always
autobiographical. The Persian Letters, one of the earliest and most famous of French novels, published
anonymously in Amsterdam and a runaway bestseller of the 1720s, was a bit of
both.
Its author, Charles-Louis de Secondes, Baron de La
Brède, Baron de Montesquieu, was born exactly one hundred years before the
convening of the first Federal Congress empowered by the American Constitution,
a document drawn up by men who knew Montesquieu who had read his books, knew
his political views by heart, and regarded him as an oracle.
The young man who brought out that first novel was far
from being an oracle, but the cast of his character was already formed. He was
bright, irreverent and fascinated by the ever-changing spectacles of 18th-century
life. The novel consists of a stream of
letters flowing back and forth between Persia and Paris. Two young
Persian noblemen, Usbek and Rica, have gone abroad to observe the exotic
customs of the Europeans, which gives the author to poke a good deal of fun at
the laws and morals, doctors and lawyers and society ladies of the Paris of
Louis XIV the "Sun King." Their letters, describing the odd and irrational ways
of the West are matched by letters written by wives and eunuchs of the harems
back in Ispahan, revealing a life even more odd and irrational. Usbek, the
mild-mannered gentleman visiting Parisian salons, is revealed as a despot at
home, with power of life and death over a number of women who are allowed to
see no other man and who have no function except to satisfy their master's
every whim. While their master sends them sprightly letters about the manners
of the infidels, the women pour out on paper their repressed sensuality, their
peevish jealousies and resentments, their tantrums. From a safe distance Usbek
tries to calm them down. The book ends melodramatically when Rosanna, the most
cherished of the wives, is caught in bed with a lover, declares her independence
and kills herself.
In real life, Montesquieu never had the bad taste to
imitate literature. No suicide, in fact no display or violent emotion of any
kind, was to mar his well-regulated existence. Passion rather bored him. One
person in love, he observed, was very much like any other, while the world of
ideas was full of infinite variety. His wide-ranging studies had taught him
that the same actions can take on very different aspects at different times and
at different places.
Like Usbek, he was an aristocrat who never had to
really worry about where the money was coming from. He had forebears in both
the sworded nobility (noblesse d'épée) which did the fighting and the gowned nobility (noblesse de robe) those highborn black-robed men who, before the
Revolution, dispensed the laws of France from seats in the regional parlements of the kingdom. Despite their name, the parlements had little in common with the English-style legislative bodies of
today. They were primarily law courts, and a seat in any one of them - like
most of the other administrative posts in the French government of the ancien
régime - was a commodity that could
be passed on by inheritance, as Montesquieu's uncle did to him, or sold to the
highest suitable bidder, as Montesquieu himself was to do at the age of 36 when
he got tired of all the paper work and needed some extra cash.
As a great landowner and a parlementaire, Montesquieu accepted the privileges and the
prejudices of his class. He knew the limitations of the parlements, but he defended them on the grounds that a man who
had put out a good deal of money to get a government office was more apt to
show independent judgment than one appointed by the king and serving at the
royal whim. Viewed from the
standpoint of today, his private life looks more like Usbek's than perhaps he
would have appreciated. His profitable marriage with a Protestant woman made
Montesquieu extremely rich, even without the fortune he would inherit from his
uncle a year later. Although he appreciated his wife (she was a first-rate
housekeeper and book-keeper), he paid as little attention to her as possible.
She remained devoted to him, competently managing the chateau and vineyards of
La Brède while he traveled, visiting the leading intellectual figures of
England, Germany and Italy, or kept up a fashionable bachelor's establishment
in Paris. He had a number of affairs with ladies of quality, some of them
stormy, but never stormy enough to disturb the equilibrium of his life. The
most important thing to know about an affair, he said, was to know how to break
it off cleanly once the thrill was gone.
At La Brède, he said affectionately, Nature wore her
bathrobe, and he regularly went back there to enjoy the grape-picking season,
staying on until he had overseen arrangements for selling his wine to
discriminating customers ll over Europe. He had three children, including a
daughter, Denise, of whom he was very fond. But noble lineages are not built on
fondness. When it became very clear that his only son was not going to have a
male heir, he married off Denise, much against her will, to a third cousin
twice her age. He was a dull creature, but the match would perpetuate the name
and keep the property in the family.
What Montesquieu considered really important, however,
was study and the play of ideas, mostly to be found in Paris where he could be free of all his family affairs. This was the great age of
witty but serious conversation, a perpetual play of give-and-take among the
finest minds of Europe. Though his ideas had their own personal coloring, they
generally reflected the climate of
the day. This was the dawn of the Enlightenment, when a radical and
sell-confident group of thinkers, known as philosophes, were proposing nothing less than tearing down the
whole structure of ideas on which European civilizations had rested for a
thousand years and putting a new one in its place.
In the world of their fathers, it was assumed that
chaos could be best kept at bay if speech, thought, trade and faith were all strictly
regulated by the central authority of church and state. Against all that, the philosophes
were now proposing freedom of thought
and speech, equality under the law, separation of church and state, religious
toleration, representative government, public education, individual rights.
Eighteenth-century intellectual activity was typically
conducted in a salon where a
society hostess would regularly invite a group of congenial people for food and
civilized talk. Like the cocktail-party, its debased modern derivative, the
salon provided an opportunity for exchanging gossip, for amatory intrigue, for
pulling delicate political strings. But its main function was to stimulate
free-wheeling discussion of new and provocative ideas. In the salons of an
expert hostess like Julie de Lespinasse, the guests were "so well assorted that
they were in harmony like the strings of an instrument in the hands of a
skilled tuner."
Whenever he visited a new town, Montesquieu liked to
climb up a high tower and get a good overall look at the place, then come down
and examine its different parts at leisure. He approached intellectual problems
in rather the same way. This was the Age of Reason, before specialists and
experts had taken over everything, and a well-educated man might well claim all
knowledge as his province. Montesquieu presented to the Academy of Bordeaux
learned papers on such heterogeneous subjects as Echoes, the Transparency of
Objects and the Uses of the Kidney Glands. He liked to make an Olympian survey
of general principles, then leap down among the details, following them with no
fixed plan, much as they might come up in a brisk conversation with such philosophes as Helvétius and Voltaire in the salons of Madame de
Tencin to Madame Geoffrin.
This was not an efficient method of studying the
physical science, but it was suited perfectly to the loose-jointed masterpiece
on which he spent more than fifteen years of his life, to which he was still
adding variations when he lay old and blind and dying at Le Brède. This work if
L'Esprit des Lois, the Spirit of
the Laws, whose more than six hundred chapters are grouped in thirty-one books.
Completed in 1745 and published in 1748, it is one of the most influential
books of all time, a treatise celebrated enough to have a big city street named
after it, Bordeaux's Boulevard de l'Esprit des Lois. It is a grab-bag of
general principles and particular observations, mixing a theory of government
and many reflections on ancient and modern history, and comments on the
influence of climate on national character, and an outline of what a hundred
years later would receive the name of sociology. The section that had the most
impact on America dealt with the separation of powers, legislative and
executive and judicial, drawn from his conversations in England with Viscount
Bolingborke.
He began with the then highly radical premise that
laws are not the result of a divine revelation to some Moses or Lycurgus or any
other of the traditional lawgivers of antiquity, but a natural evolution out of
everything that influences the life of a country, including climate, soil,
habit, tradition, history, religion and how the inhabitants make their living.
A rational man, he said, could study these matters the way Newton had studied
the natural world, and the use the knowledge to adjust the laws of his country
in the direction of greater liberty for all. As two of Montesquieu's most avid
American readers, James Madison and Alexander Hamilton, put in the Federalist papers, men were now capable of "establishing good
government from reflection and choice," instead of having to "depend for their
political constitutions on accident and force."
Madison and Hamilton were babes in arms when The
Sprit of the Law appeared in 1748.
Great Britain's colonies in North America were just that, colonies, offshoots
of the United Kingdom and proud of it. They would soon help the mother country
fight a great war against French colonists and their Indian allies to the north
and west. Nevertheless, it was in these English colonies that some of
Montesquieu's notions took deepest root.
When Americans began to grow restive under the distant
rule of England, Montesquieu's writings provided them with a framework of ideas
into which they could fit their grievances and their aspirations. In England,
Bolingbroke had taught Montesquieu to dislike the tight hold on the colonies
kept by Robert Walpole's government in London during the reigns of George I and
George II. Now the colonies could use Montesquieu to strengthen their resistance
to George III.
They believed that their rights were guaranteed by the
constitution of England., but there was no written constitution of England they
could appeal to.
In
fact, there had never been a nation anywhere in the world with a written
constitution. The English constitution was, as it still is, an unwritten
consensus of the proper rules for governing the nation, and in that consensus
Montesquieu recognized that something new had evolved, a balanced, liberal,
self-regulating form of government like nothing seen before in ancient or in
modern times. By summarizing its features - representative government,
separation of powers, individual rights - he was making a blueprint for future
creators of written constitutions.
America's founding fathers leaped on that blueprint,
especially chapters 5 and 6 of Book XI of Spirt of the Laws. There they found the definition they wanted of the
word "liberty." "Liberty is the right of doing whatever the law permits." In
other words, a law-abiding citizen has a right to be left alone. But he must
also be able to feel safe. "In order to have this liberty, it is requisite for
the government to be so constituted as one man need not be afraid of another."
England had such a government, Montesquieu believed,
and its greatest virtue was a separation of the civil authority into three
branches which did not overlap. "When the legislative and executive powers are
united in the same person, or in the same body of magistrates, there can be on
liberty...Again, there is no liberty, if the power of judging be not separated
from the legislative and elective powers."
At the Convention which the created the Constitution
of the United States of America in Philadelphia in 1787, James Madison cited
Montesquieu as his authority for insisting on the separation of executive,
legislative and judicial powers in the new government, the "checks and
balances" that have become part of the American tradition. Like several other
members of the convention he had studied The Spirit of the Laws under President Witherspoon of Princeton, who drilled
his students so thoroughly that twenty years after leaving college, Madison
could still quote whole paragraphs from memory.
Madison was no slavish disciple fo Montesquieu. H
ventured to disagree with the master when he held that republics are inherently
unstable and can exist only in a confined area, like England, with a homogenous
population. No, said Madison, in a small state or territory a majority could
act in concert and "execute plans of oppression." In an extended republic liked
the United States, on the other hand, the large number of parties made such
collusion almost impossible. "In the extent and proper structure of the Union,
we behold a republican remedy for the diseases most incident to republican government."
The very diversity of the thirteen states insured that no one group or interest
would come to dominate. This was according to Montesquieu's precepts, the
spirit of practical moderation. Compromise and adjustment were watchwords for
Montesquieu, as they were for the lawyers and planters in Philadelphia, who no
longer had a revolution to win but needed to set up a system that would work.
Both the philosophe and the
practical politicians hated extremes.
Because Montesquieu had only limited faith in the
goodness of human nature, he reasoned that anyone who possessed power would
desire to increase it, and the only way to stop him was by a system of rival
powers, a view that the Founding Fathers, fearful alike of tyranny by the many
or by the few, subscribed to. "The oracle who is always consulted and cited on
this subject," said Madison, "is the celebrated Montesquieu. If he be not the
author of the invaluable precept in the sciences of politics, he has the merit
at least of displaying and recommending it most effectually to the attention of
mankind.".
"Political liberty," he wrote, "consists in security,
or, at least, in the opinion that we enjoy security." Modern critics of U. S.
Supreme Court decisions that seen to give accused persons too many right might
ponder Montesquieu's belief that "It is on...the goodness of criminal laws that
the liberty of all subjects principally depends." He had no illusions that men
left to themselves would automatically strive for the betterment of the human
race. His historical studies had taught him how efficient and long-lasting a
despotism, based on pure terror and violence, could be. He would have put no
faith at all int eh pronouncement of another French aristocrat who played a
major role in the Enlightenment, Jefferson's friend and idol the Marquis de
Condorcet, who predicted that "the moment will come when the sun will shine on
none but free men>"
Condorcet was a much deeper and more original thinker
than Montesquieu. A mathematical genius and man of great generosity of spirit
and breadth of vision, Condorcet had every quality except common sense. He
hated Montesquieu's idea of the separation of powers because it muddied the
pure radiance of his idea of universal liberty. All power to the people, Condorcet declared, and forget all
this nonsense about checks and balances. Montesquieu could have told him (and
he did, in Book V, chapter 11) that if you start with direct rule by the people
you are apt to end up with a concentration of despotic power far worse than any
king's.
The French Revolution which began in 1789 began true
to Montesquieu's legacy, in a spirit of moderate reform but it was soon taken
over by extremists. In the name of liberty and the people, a few hundred
members of the Jacobin Club in Paris seized power and proceeded, among other
things, to condemn Condorcet to death for having opinions different from their
own..
Condorcet spent the last months of his life hiding
from Robespierre's bloodhounds, writing a voluminous work to prove by rigorous
logic that the human mind was infinitely perfectible. One day, famished and
exhausted, he stumbled into a roadside tavern and ordered an omelet. When they
asked him how many eggs he wanted in it, he didn't know what to say - a
marquis, even an impoverished revolutionary marquis like Condorcet, would never
have had any reason to be inside a kitchen - he answered at random, Twelve. Marked out at once as a
suspicious character, and certainly no child of the common people, he spent the
next two nights in jail and only escaped the guillotine by swallowing the
poison he had learned enough to always carry about his person.
Montesquieu, the wine grower who had to deal every
year with the unforgiving and unpredictable necessities of soil, climate and
human perverseness, always knew how many eggs went into his omelets. Once he
had been taken to the top of his tower, he liked to come down and feel the
earth under his feet. He had no use for the kind of philosopher who deals only
with abstract generalities.
It was that solid down-to-earth feeling which made
Montesquieu's ideas so congenial to the Madisons and Hamiltons in the American
colonies, who were trying to deal with the intractable materials of local
selfish interests and build them into a united commonwealth. And that is why
this suave, quietly ironic, long-nosed French nobleman became, in effect, the
godfather of the American Constitution.
. .
©1987 Robert Wernick
Smithsonian
Magazine